[Notes
on Husserl’s Logical Investigation Vol 2 Part 1, Introduction and LI1 §1-23]
Edmund
Husserl was born seconds before the dawn of a major revolution in the
biological sciences. Husserl was born on
April 8, 1859; Darwin’s On the Origin of
Species, was born, so to speak, seven months later (24 November 1859). By the time Darwin published The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation
to Sex in 1871, it had become abundantly clear that natural selection was
not just for beetles, birds, coral polyps and worms (some of Darwin’s favourite
organisms), but was an all encompassing mechanism that applies not only to the
anatomy of people but also to their psychological makeup, including, it would
seem, those aspects of humans that allowed them to reflect on evolutionary origins
in the first place. Darwin was well
received in the German speaking world (thanks to an early translation by Heinrich
Georg Bronn and was popularized by Ernst Haeckel) so Husserl’s formation and
early scholarship occurred at a time when the significance of the Darwinian
revolution was recognized.
Husserl
became, or course, the father of his own particular revolution; phenomenology
has arguably had an analogous influence on continental philosophy as Darwin has
had in biology, though, in fairness, it can be said that Darwin’s influence has
been more all encompassing than has phenomenology. There is, for instance, nothing comparable to
a continental-analytic divide in biology.
There are some interesting similarities between Darwin and Husserl that are
worth exploring. I’ll mention just one
point here: the foundational work of both writers was transformed quite
radically by those who came after them. In
the case of Darwin the so-called Neo-Darwinian synthesis roughly speaking
combined Darwin’s thinking with Mendelian genetics, closing the door on
Lamarckian mechanisms. Phenomenology
presented in Logical Investigations,
Husserl’s breakthrough work, was, of course, later radically transformed by
Husserl himself, but transformed in turn by Heidegger and arguably by all 20th
Century phenomenologists who worked seriously within this tradition. It seems to me that both Husserl are Darwin
are more likely to be read seriously by those looking at the history of a later
position – a sort of archeological dig – rather than for the immediate insights
they provide.
There
are very few search terms that one can submit to Google (or Google scholar… or
indeed, one supposes to Bing) that come up dry.
“Husserl and Darwin” are among those exceptional terms. Not that there is nothing, but there is very
little. Indeed, Husserl makes no
allusions, as far as I can tell, to Darwin in any of the Logical Investigations. And
certainly in LI1 he makes no reference to the history of the agent who can
communicate in expressive acts – the subject of that investigation. Darwin noted in The Descent of Man (1871) that self-consciousness has been a
characteristic of humankind and that several writers have made it the sole
distinguishing feature between humans and the “brutes” though Darwin expressed
concern about the inconsistency of definitions surrounding such debates. He does note though that “Such faculties [as
self-consciousness] could not have been fully developed in man until his mental
powers had advanced to a high standard, and this implies the use of a perfect
language.” Somewhat later in the book,
Darwin reiterates the point stating that “If it be maintained that certain
powers, such as self-consciousness, abstraction, &c., are peculiar to man,
it may well be that these are the incidental results of other highly-advanced
intellectual faculties; and these again are mainly the result of the continued
use of a highly developed language.” This putative link between consciousness (and
self-consciousness) and language might have been grist to the Husserlian mill,
but, of course, Husserl does not investigate it.
That
Husserl does not refer to Darwin is interesting, but it is somewhat trivial as
Husserl, like all of us, leaves out more major thinkers than he includes. The absence of evolution however points,
however, to an interesting lacuna in Husserl’s investigation of expression. Husserl fails to place his analysis of
expression in the context of a bio-historical development of this particularly
ability and, moreover, he does not discuss the implications of structural
differences of expression during different life stages (from childhood to old
age – for instance, is the babbling of an infant and the muttering of an old
man meaningless, or meaningless in the quite same way?) What about the difference in ability between
individuals – for example, Joyce versus, let’s say, me? Why would these somewhat obvious temporal
aspects of expressive ability not form part of the analysis (to date at least)?
Admittedly
Husserl, it would seem, is working this out the formal aspects of
expression. He makes it clear in the
introduction to Volume II Part I of the investigations that the phenomenology
he is pursuing is a “pure” philosophical discipline one that is not part of a
natural science. Thus, “all statements have a character of empirical
generality: they hold for this
nature.” (§6). Going further Husserl
emphasizes that “Phenomenology…does not discuss states of animal organisms (not
even belonging to a possible nature as such), but perceptions, judgements,
feelings as such, and what pertains
to them a priori with unlimited
generality, as pure instances of our species, of what may be seen through a
purely intuitive apprehension of essence, whether generic or specific.”
(§6) So a criticism of Husserlian
phenomenology that it is not placed in an ontogenetic context might be fended
off by those same argument with which Husserl sees off the psychologizing of logic.
So, phenomenology “lays bare the ‘sources’ from which the basic concepts
‘flow’…” The relationship then between
phenomenology and empirical sciences is that the former can be ancillary, or
perhaps more appropriately, foundational to the latter.
The
question then is whether perching phenomenology above, or rather below in an
important sense, the natural sciences and thereby proceeding with a purified philosophical
account of logic, epistemology etc. is, in fact, the most fruitful way for
phenomenology to proceed. The model is
that phenomenology steps back and then the sciences build upon phenomenological
methods. However, the observation that
we, as a species, can reflect phenomenologically and that that capacity
reflects a particular moment in biological history does not seem trivial at
all. Just as phenomenology supposedly
grounds the sciences, evolution is seen as grounding biology. When Theodosius Dobzhansky claimed that
“Nothing makes sense except in the light of evolution”, a phrase that might in
some ways be seen as a power grab in skirmishes among the biological
disciplines, it nevertheless proposes evolutionary thought as a clarifying tool
that inaugurates an examination of any biological question. Similar to the way in which, according to Husserl
at least, reasoning proceeds according
to logical rules, rather than from
logical rule (this getting logic out of a vicious circle in which it must
presupposes itself in order to progress), evolution is presupposed (because the
mind that cogitates evolutionary explanations is an evolved mind, using evolved
language) in the elaboration of evolutionary insights.
For
all of this let us not assert too strenuously phenomenology’s need for humility
and after some grumbling accept that as a pure philosophical discipline that it
can proceed and ground the sciences. Granting
this, for now at least, it may still be the case that an evolutionary sensibility,
a historicized conception of phenomenological reflection might enrich Husserl’s
account of language, which in LI1 seems idealized. As it is,
the closest that Husserl comes to speculating in a way that does not assume idealized
language use comes in §23 where Husserl performs the following thought experiment:
“If we imagine a consciousness prior to all experience, it may very well have
the same sensations as we have. But it will intuit no things, and no events
pertaining to things, it will perceive no trees and no houses, no flights of
birds nor any barking dogs.” Not only
does this come tantalizingly close to poetry in a book that otherwise reads…well,
quite unlike poetry, it suggests that Husserl sees a value to imagining a different
history. In many ways this is one of the
more provocative sections on the first investigation. It suggests that, at the very least, an evolutionary
Husserl would be interesting even if not quite so pure.
[These
are of course merely notes and very free speculation on a first reading of Logical
Investigations; if you notice anything worth correcting, or have suggestions of
useful resources, I’d be grateful to hear from you.]
No comments:
Post a Comment